Shared belief in shrinking groups - Project Site for Final Project in Logical Aspects of Multi-Agent Systems.
Like knowledge, belief can be modelled using epistemic logic, which can then be called doxastic (“belief-related”) logic. In particular, we can represent real-life situations using Kripke models , where:
Here, is the set of agents, and is the set of propositions in the language. Finally, a pointed Kripke model is a pair in which a “real world” (state ) is specified. This state is called the point.
The interpretation of the accessibility relations is as follows: when an agent can access a state from a state (i.e. ), this means that the agent holds that state for possible. Belief is then defined as follows: in a given state, an agent believes in a formula iff that formula is true in all states that the agent holds for possible. Formally, iff for all such that .
The project beliefmaker is based on the system (where is the size of ), a variant of epistemic logic which is particularly well-suited to model belief. This system is based on the following axioms (see e.g. Meyer & van der Hoek, 1995):
Axioms , , and have reasonably intuitive interpretations. First, implies that if an agent believes something, they must believe that they believe it. implies that if an agent does not believe something, they must believe that they don’t believe it. And finally, axiom implies that for every agent, there will always be a world that is in line with their beliefs (and by definition, in that world, does not hold). Each of these three axioms also restrict the class of legal -models by posing requirements on the accessibility relations. These requirements are as follows, for each relation :
The system is very similar to the system , which is often used to model knowledge. However, there is one crucial difference, reflecting the intuitive difference between knowledge and belief: when an agent knows that a formula is true, then has to be true; but when an agent merely believes , then does not have to be true (Hintakka, 1962). This means the requirements of belief are less strong than those of knowledge. This is reflected in axiom replacing ’s axiom (), which requires known facts to be true and hence requires to be not just serial, but reflexive (Meyer & van der Hoek, 1995).
There are two major notions of shared belief in a group, both of which are formalized by Kraus and Lehmann (1988), who adapt Lewis’ (2002) analysis in a doxastic context. First, a formula is generally believed in a group of agents iff it is believed by every agent in that group. This can be seen as a straightforward extension of the definition of belief in one agent. Formally:
for all agents .
Here, can be read as “everyone believes ”.
Second, a formula is commonly believed in a group iff:
Thus, every formula which is commonly believed is also generally believed, but not vice versa. For example, suppose every member of a group believes that Covid-19 is caused by 5G internet towers, but one member still holds it for possible that another member holds it for possible that this is not the case. Then although the group generally believes that 5G causes Covid-19, the group does not commonly believe that this is the case.
In Kripke semantics, a formula is commonly believed in a specific state iff that formula holds true in all states that are accessible from , by any number of agents, in any positive number of steps. Formally:
iff for all such that is in the transitive closure of the union of the accessibility relations .
Our project beliefmaker shows how, by removing agents from a pointed Kripke model, a formula can become generally and/or commonly believed in that model. This process is outlined using a concrete example, which describes how an initial group whose members have diverse beliefs regarding Covid-19 can come, upon exclusion of members, to generally/commonly believe in a conspiracy theory.